Semantic incommensurability and empirical comparability : the case of Lorentz and Einstein

Martin Carrier

Philosophia Scientiae (2004)

  • Volume: 8, Issue: 1, page 73-94
  • ISSN: 1281-2463

Abstract

top
Semantic incommensurability is understood as non-translatability of concepts taken from different theories. My aim is to give a rational reconstruction of the notion of incommensurability underlying the writings of Feyerabend and the later Kuhn. I claim that incommensurability can be reconstructed on this basis as a coherent conception and that relevant instances can be identified. The translation failure between incommensurable concepts arises from the impossibility to jointly fulfil two conditions of adequacy that the context theory of meaning places on translations. Potential conceptual analogues either fail to preserve the conditions of application or to reproduce the relevant inferential relations. Incommensurability is thus construed as the result of a particular type of conceptual relations which is produced by the incompatibility of the pertinent theories. These conceptual relations are sufficiently tight to make an empirical comparison of the relevant theoretical assertions possible. I try to make these claims plausible by elaborating examples from classical electrodynamics and special relativity.

How to cite

top

Carrier, Martin. "Semantic incommensurability and empirical comparability : the case of Lorentz and Einstein." Philosophia Scientiae 8.1 (2004): 73-94. <http://eudml.org/doc/103718>.

@article{Carrier2004,
abstract = {Semantic incommensurability is understood as non-translatability of concepts taken from different theories. My aim is to give a rational reconstruction of the notion of incommensurability underlying the writings of Feyerabend and the later Kuhn. I claim that incommensurability can be reconstructed on this basis as a coherent conception and that relevant instances can be identified. The translation failure between incommensurable concepts arises from the impossibility to jointly fulfil two conditions of adequacy that the context theory of meaning places on translations. Potential conceptual analogues either fail to preserve the conditions of application or to reproduce the relevant inferential relations. Incommensurability is thus construed as the result of a particular type of conceptual relations which is produced by the incompatibility of the pertinent theories. These conceptual relations are sufficiently tight to make an empirical comparison of the relevant theoretical assertions possible. I try to make these claims plausible by elaborating examples from classical electrodynamics and special relativity.},
author = {Carrier, Martin},
journal = {Philosophia Scientiae},
language = {eng},
number = {1},
pages = {73-94},
publisher = {Éditions Kimé},
title = {Semantic incommensurability and empirical comparability : the case of Lorentz and Einstein},
url = {http://eudml.org/doc/103718},
volume = {8},
year = {2004},
}

TY - JOUR
AU - Carrier, Martin
TI - Semantic incommensurability and empirical comparability : the case of Lorentz and Einstein
JO - Philosophia Scientiae
PY - 2004
PB - Éditions Kimé
VL - 8
IS - 1
SP - 73
EP - 94
AB - Semantic incommensurability is understood as non-translatability of concepts taken from different theories. My aim is to give a rational reconstruction of the notion of incommensurability underlying the writings of Feyerabend and the later Kuhn. I claim that incommensurability can be reconstructed on this basis as a coherent conception and that relevant instances can be identified. The translation failure between incommensurable concepts arises from the impossibility to jointly fulfil two conditions of adequacy that the context theory of meaning places on translations. Potential conceptual analogues either fail to preserve the conditions of application or to reproduce the relevant inferential relations. Incommensurability is thus construed as the result of a particular type of conceptual relations which is produced by the incompatibility of the pertinent theories. These conceptual relations are sufficiently tight to make an empirical comparison of the relevant theoretical assertions possible. I try to make these claims plausible by elaborating examples from classical electrodynamics and special relativity.
LA - eng
UR - http://eudml.org/doc/103718
ER -

References

top
  1. [1] Allén S. (editor) 1989.— Possible Worlds in Humanities, Arts and Sciences, Berlin: de Gruyter. MR988911
  2. [2] Buchwald J. Z. (editor) 1995.— Scientific Practice. Theories and Stories of Doing Physics, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 
  3. [3] Carrier Martin 2001a.— Changing Laws and Shifting Concepts: On the Nature and Impact of Incommensurability, in [Hoyningen-Huene Sankey 2001, 65–90 ]
  4. [4] Carrier Martin 2001b.— Shifting Symbolic Structures and Changing Theories: On the Non-Translatability and Empirical Comparability of Incommensurable Theories, in [Ferrari Stamatescu 2001, 125-148 ]
  5. [5] Colodny R.G. (editor) 1965.— Beyond the Edge of Certainty, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall. 
  6. [6] Cushing J. T.1998.— Philosophical Concepts in Physics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Zbl0951.01010MR1758331
  7. [7] Darrigol Olivier 1996.— The Electrodynamic Origins of Relativity Theory, Historical Studies in the Physical and Biological Sciences, 26: 241-312. 
  8. [8] Drude, P.1900.— The Theory of Optics, New York: Dover, 1959. MR113484
  9. [9] Ferrari M. and Stamatescu I. (editors) 2001.— Symbol and Physical Knowledge. On the Conceptual Structure of Physics, Berlin: Springer. 
  10. [10] Feyerabend, Paul K.1978.— Der wissenschaftstheoretische Realismus und die Autorität der Wissenschaften (Ausgewählte Schriften I), Braunschweig: Vieweg. 
  11. [11] Feyerabend, Paul K.1981.— Realism, Rationalism and Scientific Method (Philosophical Papers 1), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981. 
  12. [12] Feyerabend, Paul K.1962.— Explanation, Reduction, and Empiricism, in [Feyerabend 1981, 44–96 ]
  13. [13] Feyerabend, Paul K.1965.— Problems of Empiricism, in [Colodny 1965, 145-260 ]
  14. [14] Feyerabend, Paul K.1972.— Die Wissenschaftstheorie—eine bisher unerforschte Form des Irrsinns?, in [Feyerabend 1978, 293-338 ]
  15. [15] French A. P.1968.— Special Relativity, Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press. 
  16. [16] Hon G.1995.— Is the Identification of Experimental Error Contextually Dependent? The Case of Kaufmann’s Experiment and Its Varied Reception, in [Buchwald 1995, 170-223 ]
  17. [17] Horwich P. (editor) 1993.— World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science, Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press. MR1222714
  18. [18] Hoyningen-Huene Paul 1989.— Die Wissenschaftsphilosophie Thomas S. Kuhns, Braunschweig: Vieweg. 
  19. [19] Hoyningen-Huene P. and Sankey H. (editors) 2001.— Incommensurability and Related Matters, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Dordrecht: Kluwer. 
  20. [20] Irzik G. and Grünberg T.1995.— Carnap and Kuhn: Arch Enemies or Close Allies, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46: 285–307. MR1353731
  21. [21] Irzik G. and Grünberg T.1998.— Whorfian Variations on Kantian Themes: Kuhn’s Linguistic Turn, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29: 207–221. 
  22. [22] Krüger L. et al. (editors) 1987.— The Probabilistic Revolution I: Ideas in History, Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press, MR929849
  23. [23] Kuhn Thomas S.1962.— The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Second edition, 1970. 
  24. [24] Kuhn Thomas S.1983.— Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability, PSA 1982. II, East Lansing Mich.: PSA: 669-688. 
  25. [25] Kuhn Thomas S.1987.— What are Scientific Revolutions?, in [Krüger 1987, 7-22 ] MR929850
  26. [26] Kuhn Thomas S.1989.— Possible Worlds in History of Science, in [Allén 1989–32 ]
  27. [27] Kuhn Thomas S.1990.— The Road since Structure, PSA 1990. II, East Lansing Mich.: PSA 1991: 3-13. 
  28. [28] Kuhn Thomas S.1993.— Afterwords, in [Horwich 1993, 311-341 ]
  29. [29] Lorentz H. A.1899.— Simplified Theory of Electrical and Optical Phenomena in Moving Systems, in [Schaffner 1972, 255-273 ]
  30. [30] McCormmach R.1970.— Einstein, Lorentz, and the Electron Theory, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 2: 41-87. 
  31. [31] Miller A. I.1981.— Albert Einstein’s Special Theory of Relativity. Emergence (1905) and Early Interpretation (1905-1911), Reading Mass.: Addison-Wesley. MR604013
  32. [32] Nersessian N. J.1986.— Why Wasn’t Lorentz Einstein?, An Examination of the Scientific Method of H.A. Lorentz, Centaurus, 29: 205–242. MR878443
  33. [33] Papineau D.1979.— Theory and Meaning, Oxford: Clarendon Press. 
  34. [34] Sankey H.1994.— The Incommensurability Thesis, Aldershot: Ashgate. 
  35. [35] Schaffner K.1972.— Nineteenth-Century Aether Theories, Oxford: Pergamon Press. 
  36. [36] Schaffner K.1974.— Einstein versus Lorentz: Research Programmes and the Logic of Comparative Theory Evaluation, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25: 45–78. 

NotesEmbed ?

top

You must be logged in to post comments.

To embed these notes on your page include the following JavaScript code on your page where you want the notes to appear.

Only the controls for the widget will be shown in your chosen language. Notes will be shown in their authored language.

Tells the widget how many notes to show per page. You can cycle through additional notes using the next and previous controls.

    
                

Note: Best practice suggests putting the JavaScript code just before the closing </body> tag.